|
In mathematical logic, reduction to Skolem normal form (SNF) is a method for removing existential quantifiers from formal logic statements, often performed as the first step in an automated theorem prover. A formula of first-order logic is in Skolem normal form (named after Thoralf Skolem) if it is in prenex normal form with only universal first-order quantifiers. Every first-order formula may be converted into Skolem normal form while not changing its satisfiability via a process called Skolemization (sometimes spelled "Skolemnization"). The resulting formula is not necessarily equivalent to the original one, but is equisatisfiable with it: it is satisfiable if and only if the original one is satisfiable.〔(【引用サイトリンク】url=http://www.mpi-inf.mpg.de/departments/rg1/teaching/autrea-ss10/script/lecture10.pdf )〕 The simplest form of Skolemization is for existentially quantified variables which are not inside the scope of a universal quantifier. These may be replaced simply by creating new constants. For example, may be changed to , where is a new constant (does not occur anywhere else in the formula). More generally, Skolemization is performed by replacing every existentially quantified variable with a term whose function symbol is new. The variables of this term are as follows. If the formula is in prenex normal form, are the variables that are universally quantified and whose quantifiers precede that of . In general, they are the variables that are quantified universally and such that occurs in the scope of their quantifiers. The function introduced in this process is called a Skolem function (or Skolem constant if it is of zero arity) and the term is called a Skolem term. As an example, the formula is not in Skolem normal form because it contains the existential quantifier . Skolemization replaces with , where is a new function symbol, and removes the quantification over . The resulting formula is . The Skolem term contains , but not , because the quantifier to be removed is in the scope of , but not in that of ; since this formula is in prenex normal form, this is equivalent to saying that, in the list of quantifers, precedes while does not. The formula obtained by this transformation is satisfiable if and only if, the original formula is. ==How Skolemization works== Skolemization works by applying a second-order equivalence in conjunction to the definition of first-order satisfiability. The equivalence provides a way for "moving" an existential quantifier before a universal one. : where : is a function that maps to . Intuitively, the sentence "for every there exists a such that " is converted into the equivalent form "there exists a function mapping every into a such that, for every it holds ". This equivalence is useful because the definition of first-order satisfiability implicitly existentially quantifies over the evaluation of function symbols. In particular, a first-order formula is satisfiable if there exists a model and an evaluation of the free variables of the formula that evaluate the formula to ''true''. The model contains the evaluation of all function symbols; therefore, Skolem functions are implicitly, existentially quantified. In the example above, is satisfiable if and only if, there exists a model , which contains an evaluation for , such that is true for some evaluation of its free variables (none in this case). This may be expressed in second order as . By the above equivalence, this is the same as the satisfiability of . At the meta-level, first-order satisfiability of a formula may be written with a little abuse of notation as , where is a model, is an evaluation of the free variables, and means that is true in under . Since first-order models contain the evaluation of all function symbols, any Skolem function contains is implicitly, existentially quantified by . As a result, after replacing an existential quantifier over variables into an existential quantifiers over functions at the front of the formula, the formula still may be treated as a first-order one by removing these existential quantifiers. This final step of treating as may be completed because functions are implicitly existentially quantified by in the definition of first-order satisfiability. Correctness of Skolemization may be shown on the example formula as follows. This formula is satisfied by a model if and only if, for each possible value for in the domain of the model there exists a value for in the domain of the model that makes true. By the axiom of choice, there exists a function such that . As a result, the formula is satisfiable, because it has the model obtained by adding the evaluation of to . This shows that is satisfiable only if is satisfiable as well. In the other way around, if is satisfiable, then there exists a model that satisfies it; this model includes an evaluation for the function such that, for every value of , the formula holds. As a result, is satisfied by the same model because one may choose, for every value of , the value , where is evaluated according to . 抄文引用元・出典: フリー百科事典『 ウィキペディア(Wikipedia)』 ■ウィキペディアで「Skolem normal form」の詳細全文を読む スポンサード リンク
|